Rice’s theorem
We will now prove another fundamental result of computability theory, which is known as Rice’s theorem.
Rice’s theorem says that telling what a computer program does from looking at its source code is either trivial or impossible.
We can state this in a more mathematical way. Let
\[\mathcal{F} \subseteq \mathcal{PR}\]be some set of computable functions. Recall that
\[\mathcal{PR} = \{ f : \mathbb{N} ⇀ \mathbb{N} \mid \text{$f = ⟦ P ⟧_{\texttt{x}}$ for some While program $P$ } \}\]is the set of all computable functions. $\mathcal{F}$ picks out only some of them, which we will regard as the “good” computable functions.
We would like to be able to tell whether a computable function $f$ is “good”, i.e. in $\mathcal{F}$, just by looking at its source code.
Example 1
Suppose that we want to decide whether a program returns $0$ when given input $0$. This amounts to asking whether the function it computes is in the set
\[\mathcal{F}_0 = \{\ f : \mathbb{N} ⇀ \mathbb{N} \in \mathcal{PR} \mid f(0) \simeq 0 \}\]of computable functions that return $0$ on input $0$. ▣
Example 2
Suppose that we want to decide whether a program terminates on all inputs. This amounts to asking whether the function it computes is in the set
\[\mathcal{T} = \{\ f : \mathbb{N} ⇀ \mathbb{N} \in \mathcal{PR} \mid \text{$f$ is total, i.e. } \forall n. f(n) \downarrow \}\]of computable functions that are also total. ▣
Reflecting into the natural numbers
Given any predicate $\mathcal{F} \subseteq \mathbb{N} ⇀ \mathbb{N}$ on functions, we can reflect it on the natural numbers under the Gödel numbering. That is, we can define the set
\[F = \{ \ulcorner S \urcorner \mid ⟦ S ⟧_\texttt{x} \in \mathcal{F} \}\]of (Gödel numbers of) programs which compute only “good” functions.
Example 1
Reflecting $\mathcal{F}_0$, we obtain the set
\[F_0 = \{ \ulcorner S \urcorner \mid ⟦ S ⟧_\texttt{x}(0) \simeq 0 \}\]which contains the (Gödel numbers of) programs which output $0$ on input $0$. ▣
Example 2
Reflecting $\mathcal{T}$, we obtain the set
\[T = \{ \ulcorner S \urcorner \mid ⟦ S ⟧_\texttt{x}(0) \text{ is a total function } \}\]which contains the (Gödel numbers of) programs which terminate on any input. ▣
Statement of the theorem
We then have the
Theorem (Rice). For any $\mathcal{F}$ of computable functions that is not trivial (either the empty set, or the set of all computable functions), the reflected set $F$ is undecidable.
The proof of Rice’s theorem is by reduction.
Intuition
Recall the notion of static analysis from our discussion of the Halting Problem.
A static analyzer is supposed to go through a program and detect bad behaviours that might arise during runtime.
Thus, given a program $S$, a static analyzer is supposed to be able to tell something about the function $⟦ S ⟧_\texttt{x}$ that it computes.
Rice’s theorem states that it making a static analyzer is impossible. Asking whether the function $⟦ S ⟧_\texttt{x}$ belongs to a class of desirable functions $\mathcal{F}$ is an unsolvable problem (as long as $\mathcal{F}$ is neither “no functions” nor “all functions”, in which case the answer is trivial).
The definition of decidability asks for perfect static analysis: the set $F$ is decidable if, upon seeing the source code $S$, we can tell with certainty whether $S$ is good or $S$ is bad. Rice’s theorem proves that we can never be that certain.
Then, how do we have static analyzers in practice? The reason is that the static analyzers we use in real life are imperfect. Sometimes they fail to catch all errors. Sometimes they report errors when there aren’t any - i.e. they are too conservative.